physics, mathematical physics, philosophy of physics
theory (physics), model (physics)
experiment, measurement, computable physics
Axiomatizations
Tools
Structural phenomena
Types of quantum field thories
In physics, the term general covariance is meant to indicate the property of a physical system or model (in theoretical physics) whose configurations, action functional and equations of motion are all equivariant under the action of the diffeomorphism group on the smooth manifold underlying the spacetime or the worldvolume of the system. Here “covariance” is as in “covariant tensor” another term for behaviour under diffeomorphisms.
The term general relativity for Einstein-gravity originates in at least closely related ideas (see History and original formulation below), and Einstein-gravity is the archtypical example of a generally covariant physical system:
here, the configuration space of physical fields over a smooth manifold is not quite the space of Riemannian metrics on itself, but is the quotient of this space by the action of the diffeomorphism group : two Riemannian metrics and on represent the same field of gravity on if there is a diffeomorphism such that .
Or rather, such a diffeomorphism is a gauge transformation between the two field configurations. The configuration space is not the naive quotient of fields by diffeomorphisms as above, but is the homotopy quotient, or action groupoid, denoted . In the physics literature this action groupoid is most familiar in its infinitesimal approximation, the corresponding Lie algebroid, whose formal dual is a BRST complex whose degree-1 elements are accordingly called the diffeomorphism ghosts (see there).
As with all gauge transformations, they relate physical configurations which may be nominally different, but equivalent. Therefore general covariance is an instance of the general principle of equivalence in mathematics which says that sensible statements about objects must respect the isomorphisms and more general equivalences between these objects.
A physical system which is not generally covariant in this sense is hence one where the smooth manifold as above, underlying spacetime/worldvolume is not regarded as modelling an absolute physical system (such as the observable universe in gravity), but a subsystem that is equipped with ambient structure that breaks the diffeomorphism symmetry. Notably systems like electromagnetism or Yang-Mills theory have traditionally been written in a non-generally covariant form describing gauge fields on a fixed gravitational background, as for instance the space inhabited by a particle accelerator. This ambient structure on the spacetime breaks its general diffeomorphism invariance and hence the effective resulting theory on this background is not generally covariant (a special case of the general phenomenon of spontaneous symmetry breaking).
On the other hand, such a model consisting of background (e.g. the particle accelerator) and quantum fields propagating in it is ultimately to be understood as an approximation to a more encompassing model in which also the background is dynamical, and which is again generally covariant. Specific for electromagnetism and Yang-Mills theory this refined generally covariant model is known as Einstein-Maxwell theory or more generally Einstein-Yang-Mills theory.
The idea of general covariance has a long and convoluted history and the literature witnesses plenty of disagreement about how to interpret and formalize it in technical detail (Norton). Already early arguments by Einstein himself (e.g. the “hole paradox” (Einstein-Grossmann)) show that the discussion has suffered from the beginning from lack of the basic category theoretic concept of isomorphism in the category Diff of smooth manifolds. Below in Formalization in homotopy type theory we indicate a formalization of general covariance that is general, fundamental, and accurately reflects the role of the term in theoretical physics.
The question of general covariance of physical theories in space and time can be traced back to the famous debate between Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz and Samuel Clarke (the latter assisted by Sir Isaac Newton) on the ontological status of space in the years 1715–1716 (Alexander), the central question being if space exists as a substance or as an absolute being and absolute motion is present (Clarke) or if it is constituted only in relation to co-existent things allowing for relativism in motions only (Leibniz). This kind of problems also played an important role when the general theory of relativity was being developed in the years around 1910. While Albert Einstein first characterized generally covariant field equations as inadmissible since they did not determine the metric field uniquely as shown in the hole argument ( Lochbetrachtung ) in the appendix of (Einstein-Grossmann), he later accepted (Einstein 1916) that all physical laws had to be expressed by equations that are valid in all coordinate systems, i. e., which are covariant (generally covariant) under arbitrary substitutions.
Die allgemeinen Naturgesetze sind durch Gleichungen auszudrücken, die für alle Koordinatensysteme gelten, d. h. die beliebigen Substitutionen gegenüber kovariant (allgemein kovariant) sind. (Einstein 1916 p. 776)
The hole argument was dismissed by the reasoning that it is not the spacetime metric that has to be fixed uniquely by the field equations, but only the physical phenomena that occur in spacetime need to be given a unique expression with reference to any description of spacetime. All physical statements are given in terms of spacetime coincidences; measurements result in statements on meetings of material points of the measuring rods with other material points or in coincidences between watch hands and points on the clockface. The introduction of a reference system merely serves the easy description of the totality of all these coincidences (point-coincidence argument) (Einstein 1916 p. 776f).
from (Brunetti-Pormann-Ruzzi)
We discuss the modern formulation of general covariance in differential geometry.
Let SmoothMfd be a smooth manifold. Write for the space of (pseudo-)Riemannian metrics on . For a diffeomorphism, there is a function which sends a Riemannian metric to its pullback:
where is the canonical map induced on the tangent bundle (see at derivative).
Say that two metrics are gauge equivalent if there is a diffeomorphism such that . This is an equivalence relation. Write for the corresponding set of equivalence classes.
The statement of general covariance is that the distinct configurations of the gravitational field form the set . In particular, if is compact, then the Einstein-Hilbert action functional which a priori is defined on descends to
While this captures the idea of general covariance accurately, for further development of the theory of gravity, however, the set needs to be refined. It is really equipped with the structure of a smooth space (in order to perform variational calculus and hence derive the equations of motion of the theory), and second it is to be refined to a smooth groupoid .
Finally, for setups that admit to introduce fermions/spinors into the model one needs to refine Riemannian metrics to vielbein fields/orthogonal structures. The fully refined generally covariance smooth configuration groupoid is then , discussed in more detail below.
The principle of equivalence in general relativity is formally the statement that around every point in a (pseudo-)Riemannian manifold one can find a coordinate system such that the Levi-Civita connection vanishes (“Riemann normal coordinates”), which means that to first infinitesimal order around that point particle dynamics subject to the force of gravity is equivalent to dynamics in Minkowski spacetime with vanishing field of gravity.
By the above, this is a special case of the principle of general covariance: for every field configuration and every given point there is a gauge equivalent field configuration such that the “force of gravity” (the Levi-Civita connection) vanishes at that point.
It is via this relation that the physical “principle of equivalence” relates to the mathematical principle of equivalence: this says that formulations need to respect the given notion of equivalence/gauge transformation, and so
principle of equivalence in mathematics principle of general covariance principle of equivalence in physics .
We discuss here that general covariance in field theory has a natural formalization in homotopy type theory, hence internal to any (∞,1)-topos. For exposition, background and further details on the discussion of classical/quantum field theory in this fashion see (Schreiber, ESI lectures) and (Schreiber-Shulman).
The same kind of construction yields important moduli stacks, for instance the moduli stack of Riemann surfaces, see this remark there.
Let be a smooth manifold to be thought of as spacetime.
Then the central idea of general covariance is that for
and
two subsets/submanifolds, they should be regarded as equivalent if there is a diffeomorphism which takes one to the other, hence such that .
That this statement can be puzzling if one thinks of the case as being just a single point is the content of the historical “hole argument paradox”.
But with just a little bit of formalization the apparent paradox is resolved, because the above evidently just says that the “moduli space” for “subsets of spacetime” is not the manifold itself, but is rather a “moduli stack” namely the quotient stack of by the action of the diffeomorphism group.
Indeed, the technical term “quotient stack” is precisely defined by the condition that for of the shape of a disk/coordinate chart, then two maps
to it are equivalent if (and only if) there is a diffeomorphism relating them, as above.
So if in a generally covariant field theory spacetime is not actually the manifold , but rather the quotient stack , then also a field in this generally covariant field theory should be a field on that quotient stack, not on itself.
For a moduli space/moduli stack of fields, in a non-generally covariant field theory a field configuration is simply a map
and accordingly the space of all field configurations is the mapping space .
From this it is clear that for a generally covariant field theory we are instead to declare that the space of field configurations is
And it is at this point that the formalism of homotopy type theory/higher topos theory works a little wonder for us. Namely the formalism allows us to prove, and this is what is discussed below, that
In words, the right hand side is the time-honored answer: two fields on a spacetime manifold which are such that one goes over into the other when pulled back along a diffeomorphism are gauge equivalent. This is the statement of general covariance, derived here, formally, from just the condition that any two shapes in spacetime are to be equivalent if related by a diffeomorphism.
Here to read the above equivalence as a theorem, we have to read the left hand side, as it should, be “in the context of -actions”. Such context-dependence is precisely what dependent homotopy type theory takes care of, and this is what the following technical statement deals with.
A basic idea of traditional dependent type theory is of course that types may appear in context of other types . The traditional interpretation of such a dependent type
is that of a -parameterized family or bundle of types, whose fiber over is .
But in homotopy type theory, types are homotopy types and, hence so are the contexts. A type in context is now in general something more refined than just a family of types. It is really a family of types equipped with equivariance structure with respect to the homotopy groups of the context type.
Hence in homotopy theory types in context generically satisfy an equivariance-principle.
Specifically, if the context type is connected and pointed, then it is equivalent to the delooping of an ∞-group . One finds – this is discussed at ∞-action – that the context defined by the type is that of -equivariance: every type in the context is a type in the original context, but now equipped with a -∞-action. In a precise sense, the homotopy type theory of --actions is equivalent to plain homotopy type theory in context .
In the following we discuss this for the case that is an automorphism ∞-group of a type which is regarded as representing spacetime or a worldvolume. We show that in this context the rules of homotopy type theory automatically induce the principle of general covariance and naturally produce configurations spaces of generally covariant field theories: for a moduli object for the given fields, so that a field configuration is a function , the configuration space of covariant fields is the function type but formed in the “general covariance context” . When interpreted in smooth models, is the smooth groupoid of field configurations and diffeomorphism gauge transformations acting on them, the Lie integrations of the BRST complex whose degree-1 elements are the diffeomorphism ghosts.
More precisely, we show the following.
Consider in homotopy type theory two types , to be called spacetime and field moduli. Let
be the image of the name of , with essentially unique term
Perform the canonical context extension of and trivial context extension of to get types in context
and
Form then the type of field moduli “” in this context:
The categorical semantics of in the model Smooth∞Grpd of the homotopy type theory and for SmoothMfd is given by the diffeological groupoid
whose objects are field configurations on and whose morphisms are diffeomorphism gauge transformations between them. In particular the corresponding Lie algebroid is dual to the BRST complex of fields with diffeomorphism ghosts in degree 1.
Write for the ambient homotopy type theory, or rather an interpretation given by an (∞,1)-topos. For standard applications in physics we have Smooth∞Grpd or SmoothSuper∞Grpd or similar, but none of the following general discussion depends on a concrete choice for .
Pick once and for all an object
supposed to represent the space underlying spacetime or the worldvolume of a model (in theoretical physics),
Write
for the automorphism ∞-group of . As discussed there, this is the loop space object of the homotopy image-factorization of
hence the factorization by an effective epimorphism followed by a monomorphism:
In the standard interpretation of the homotopy type theory in Smooth∞Grpd could be an ordinary smooth manifold or orbifold, in particular, and then is the diffeomorphism group of , regarded as a diffeological group object. In view of this archetypical example we will in the following often say diffeomorphism for short instead of auto-equivalence in and similarly refer to loosely as the diffeomorphism group of . But even in the specifical model Smooth∞Grpd/SmoothSuper∞Grpd, can be much more general than a smooth manifold or supermanifold or orbifold.
Write then for the delooping of the diffeomorphism group. The essentially unique term of this type is to be thought of as being itself, and so we write it as
By the discussion at ∞-action, a type in context of
is a type in the absolute context equipped with an -∞-action on it. The dependent sum
which we also write
is the total space of the universal associated -fiber ∞-bundle:
Hence the interpretation of the context is the slice (∞,1)-topos and equivalently is the (∞,1)-topos of objects in equipped with -∞-actions and of -equivariant morphisms between them:
Hence a type in context is a “generally covariant type” with respect to in the sense that it transforms covariantly by equivalences under diffeomorphisms of . In summary then
Fact. is the context of general covariance with respect to .
In the precise formal sense.
In particular, itself is canonically equipped with the defining action of on it, which syntactically we may write
and which semantically is exhibited by the universal associated -fiber ∞-bundle
given by the pullback of the universe along the defining inclusion .
Here the total space
is the homotopy quotient or action groupoid of by . This is the type characterized by the fact that a function is a function to which is regarded as (gauge) equivalent to another function to if both differ by postcomposition with a diffeomorphism of .
Let now
be an object that represents the moduli ∞-stack of field configurations on for some model (in theoretical physics) to be described. For instance for an ∞-group and a cohesive homotopy type theory, we could have the moduli for a choice of -principal ∞-connection, being the moduli for -(higher)gauge fields. For general we may always regard as the target space of a sigma-model.
Then the internal hom
hence the function type
is the naive configuration space of the model. This is not generally covariant, precisely so by the above definition: it is not in the generally covariant context .
But by the inverse image of the -dependent product étale geometric morphism
which is context enlargement by , the moduli type is freely moved to the general covariant context, where it is regarded as equipped with the trivial ∞-action. Accordingly we will write just with that trivial action understood, which is justified by the precise syntactic expression for it:
We may then form the configuration space of fields in the generally covariant context . As before, a field should be a function on with values in the moduli type of field configurations, but now we interpret this statement in the generally covariant context. Syntactically this simply means that a field is now a term in -context
and that accordingly the configuration space of fields is
The semantics of this is the internal hom in the slice (∞,1)-topos, the Internal hom of ∞-actions
The central observation now is that discussed at ∞-action – Examples – General covariance:
is the homotopy quotient of the naive fields by the action of the diffeomorphism group, exhibiting a gauge equivalence between any two field configurations that differ after pullback along a diffeomorphism.
This is precisely as it should be for configuration space of generally covariant theories. We have found:
Fact. In terms of homotopy type theory, configuration spaces of a generally covariant theory over are precisely the ordinary configuration spaces of fields, but formed in the context :
We now spell out the example of ordinary Einstein-gravity in this language. Plenty of further examples work analogously.
For pure gravity, we choose Smooth∞Grpd or SynthDiff∞Grpd.
If we denote by SynthDiff∞Grpd the first order infinitesimal neighbourhood of the origin in the Cartesian space , then
is the automorphism ∞-group of . Accordingly we write the unique term of the delooping as
The fields of Einstein gravity are orthogonal structures (Riemannian metrics) on a smooth manifold SmoothMfd of dimension . As discussed at orthogonal structure and vielbein, we are to regard in the context of the delooping of the general linear group via its tangent bundle , by which we always mean here the -principal bundle to which the tangent bundle is associated.
By the discussion at principal ∞-bundle this is modulated by a morphism
to the delooping of (the moduli stack of -principal bundles) in that we have a fiber sequence
in . (A detailed exposition of this and the following, with further pointers, is in (Schreiber, ESI lectures).)
Therefore the syntax of the tangent bundle as a dependent type is
and since is essentially unique we will notationally suppress it in the succedent on the right and just write
Let then
be the delooping of the inclusion of the maximal compact subgroup of , the orthogonal group , regarded as an object in the slice-(∞,1)-topos over . Since this sits in the homotopy fiber sequence
with the coset smooth space , the syntax of this object is the dependent type
In view of the equivalence of (∞,1)-categories
this expresses the canonical -action on the coset (by mutliplication from the “other side”).
The syntax of the moduli stack of vielbein fields / Riemannian metrics on is
This almost verbatim expresses the familiar statement:
A vielbein on is a -equivariant map from to the coset .
The categorical semantics of such a vielbein is as a diagram
This in turn almost verbatim expresses the familar equivalent statement
A vielbein is a reduction of the structure group of the -principal bundle along .
This is still the naive space of fields, not yet generally covariant. So we next pass to the general covariant -context and form the correct generally covariant space of fields, being the type in context given by
which is the integrated BRST complex of Einstein gravity field configurations modulo diffeomorphism ghosts: the smooth groupoid whose
morphisms are
orthogonal frame transformations of the fibers of the tangent bundle;
general diffeomorphisms of the base .
We unwind this a bit more.
A slight subtlety in interpreting the above expression is that in
the automorphism ∞-group of the tangent bundle it to be formed in the context of . By the discussion at automorphism ∞-group the delooping is the ∞-image of the name
of in the slice. By the discussion at slice-(∞,1)-topos – Object classifier the object classifier in the slice is the projection .
So the name and its pullback are given by a diagram of the form
in . Here the ∞-image is directly read off to be the factorization in the third column of
where each square and hence each rectangle is an (∞,1)-pullback in . This shows that the automorphism -group of in the context of is just the absolute automorphism -group freely context extended. The categorical semantics of the dependent type
is the third column from the left in the above diagram. This means that the dependent sum in
forms the internal hom in between the homotopy fiber of that third column formed in , which is the second column (and therefore now does rememeber the -action on ) with , rememeberting that the result has an -action by precomposition.
The pre-history of the idea of general covariance is reviewed in
The original articles by Einstein on the idea of general covariance include his Entwurf (sketch)
of the theory of gravity (where the notion of general covariance is still rejected) and then the full development of general relativity
where it is fully embraced.
An attempt at a fairly comprehensive review of the history of the idea of general covariance and its reception up to modern days is in
A formalization in the context of AQFT is proposed and discussed in
Klaus Fredenhagen, Rudolf Haag, Generally covariant quantum field theory and scaling limits, Comm. Math. Phys. Volume 108, Number 1 (1987), 91-115. (EUCLID)
Romeo Brunetti, Klaus Fredenhagen, Rainer Verch, The generally covariant locality principle – A new paradigm for local quantum physics, Commun.Math.Phys.237:31-68,2003 (math-ph/0112041)
A review is in
For more see the references at AQFT on curved spacetimes.
Background and context for the above formalization of classical/quantum field theory in homotopy type theory see
See also higher category theory and physics.
Last revised on October 5, 2017 at 09:46:39. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.